Zeno's paradoxes
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Zeno's paradoxes are a set of problems devised by Zeno of Elea to support Parmenides' doctrine that "all is one" and that contrary to the evidence of our senses, the belief in plurality and change is mistaken, and in particular that motion is nothing but an illusion.
Several of Zeno's eight surviving paradoxes(preserved in Aristotle's Physics and Simplicius's commentary thereon) are essentially equivalent to one another; and most of them were regarded, even in ancient times, as very easy to refute. Three of the strongest and most famous—that of Achilles and the tortoise, the dichotomy argument, and that of an arrow in flight—are given here.
Zeno's arguments are perhaps the first examples of a method of proof called reductio ad absurdum also known as proof by contradiction. They are also credited as a source of the dialectic method used by Socrates.
According to some historians of philosophy[citation needed], Zeno's paradoxes were a major problem for ancient and medieval philosophers.
In modern times, Calculus has been widely accepted by mathematicians and engineers as at least a practical solution for calculating infinitesimal distances. Other proposed solutions to Zeno's paradoxes from past and present philosophers[citation needed] have included the denial that space and time are themselves infinitely divisible, and the denial that the terms space and time refer to any entity with any innate properties at all.
Many philosophers still hesitate to say that all paradoxes are completely solved[citation needed]. Some philosophers[citation needed] state that these paradoxes still have modern relevance: attempts to deal with the paradoxes have resulted in intellectual discoveries[citation needed] and variations on the paradoxes (see Thomson's lamp) continue to produce at least temporary puzzlement in discovering what, if anything, is wrong with the argument.
The origins of the paradoxes are somewhat unclear. Diogenes Laertius says that Zeno's teacher, Parmenides, was "the first to use the argument known as 'Achilles and the Tortoise' ", and attributes this assertion to Favorinus. In a later statement, Laertius attributed the paradoxes to Zeno.
[edit] Paradoxes of motion
[edit] Achilles and the tortoise
"You can never catch up."
- "In a race, the quickest runner can never overtake the slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point whence the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold a lead." (Aristotle Physics VI:9, 239b15)
In the paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise, we imagine the Greek hero Achilles in a footrace with the plodding reptile. Because he is such a fast runner, Achilles graciously allows the tortoise a head start of a hundred feet. If we suppose that each racer starts running at some constant speed (one very fast and one very slow), then after some finite time, Achilles will have run a hundred feet, bringing him to the tortoise's starting point; during this time, the tortoise has "run" a (much shorter) distance, say one foot. It will then take Achilles some further period of time to run that distance, in which said period the tortoise will advance farther; and then another period of time to reach this third point, while the tortoise moves ahead. Thus, whenever Achilles reaches somewhere the tortoise has been, he still has farther to go. Therefore, Zeno says, swift Achilles can never overtake the tortoise. Thus, while common sense and common experience would hold that one runner can catch another, according to the above argument, he cannot; this is the paradox.
[edit] The dichotomy paradox
"You cannot even start."
- "That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal." (Aristotle Physics VI:9, 239b10)
Suppose Homer wants to catch a stationary bus. Before he can get there, he must get halfway there. Before he can get halfway there, he must get a quarter of the way there. Before traveling a quarter, he must travel one-eighth; before an eighth, one-sixteenth; and so on.
The resulting sequence can be represented as:
This description requires one to complete an infinite number of steps, which Zeno maintains is an impossibility.
This sequence also presents a second problem in that it contains no first distance to run, for any possible first distance could be divided in half, and hence would not be first after all. Hence, the trip cannot even begin. The paradoxical conclusion then would be that travel over any finite distance can neither be completed nor begun, and so all motion must be an illusion.
This argument is called the Dichotomy because it involves repeatedly splitting a distance into two parts. It contains some of the same elements as the Achilles and the Tortoise paradox, but with a more apparent conclusion of motionlessness. It is also known as the Race Course paradox.
[edit] The arrow paradox
"You cannot even move."
“ | If everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest, and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. | ” |
Finally, in the arrow paradox, we imagine an arrow in flight. At every moment in time, the arrow is located at a specific position. If the moment is just a single instant, then the arrow does not have time to move and is at rest at that instant. Now, in following instants, it then must also be at rest for the same reason. The arrow is always at rest and cannot move: motion is impossible.
This paradox is also known as the fletcher's paradox, where a fletcher is a maker of arrows.
Whereas the first two paradoxes presented divide space into segments, this paradox divides time into points.
[edit] Proposed solutions
[edit] Proposed solutions to the arrow paradox
Aristotle, who recorded Zeno's arguments in his work Physics disputes Zeno's reasoning. Aristotle denies that time is composed of "nows", as implied by Zeno's argument. If there is just a collection of "nows" then there is no such thing as temporal magnitude. Therefore, if Aristotle is correct in denying that time is composed of indivisible "nows", then Zeno is wrong in saying that the arrow was stationary throughout its flight despite saying that in each "now" the moving arrow is at rest.
According to Zeno, at any instant, the arrow must be at rest. However, this has been disputed, since being at rest is a relative term. One cannot judge, from observing any one instant, that the arrow is at rest. Rather, one requires other, adjacent instants to assert whether, compared to other instants, the arrow at one instant is at rest. Thus, compared to other instants, if the arrow is found to be at a different place than it was and will be at the times before and after, then we have reason to claim the arrow has moved.
A mathematical account would be as follows: in the limit, as the length of a moment approaches zero, the instantaneous rate of change or velocity (which is the quotient of distance over length of the moment) does not have to approach zero. This nonzero limit is the velocity of the arrow at the instant.
The concepts involved in this paradox are in some ways reminiscent of Heisenberg's Uncertainty principle in which as we become more precise in locating the position of quantum particles, we necessarily become less precise about their momentum — and thus about their velocity.
[edit] Proposed solutions both to Achilles and the tortoise, and to the dichotomy
Both the paradoxes of Achilles and the tortoise and that of the dichotomy depend on dividing distances into a sequence of distances that become progressively smaller, and so are subject to the same counter-arguments.
Aristotle pointed out that as the distance decreases, the time needed to cover those distances also decreases, so that the time needed also becomes increasingly small. Such an approach to solving the paradoxes would amount to a denial that it must take an infinite amount of time to traverse an infinite sequence of distances.
Before 212 BCE, Archimedes had developed a method to derive a finite answer for the sum of infinitely many terms that get progressively smaller. Theorems have been developed in more modern calculus to achieve the same result, but with a more rigorous proof of the method. These methods allow construction of solutions stating that (under suitable conditions) if the distances are always decreasing, the time is finite.
[edit] Proposed solution using mathematical series notation
Several proposed solutions have at their core geometric series. A general geometric series can be written as
which is convergent and equal to a/(1−x) provided that |x| < 1 (otherwise the series diverges). Again, if we attempted to solve for a/(1−1) − a/0 we are back to the problem that nothing can be divided by 0. The geometric series that would solve this to convergence reflects our perceived reality, if 0 were that point at which there were no more distance to travel and the destination had been reached. Albert Einstein had written that "what we are sure about in reality is not reflected in mathematics and what we're sure about in mathematics is not reflected in reality." This paradox on the surface is a reflection of the conundrum of math vs reality.
Although these proposed solutions effectively involve dividing up the distance to be travelled into smaller and smaller pieces, it is easier to conceive of the solution as Aristotle did, by considering the time it takes Achilles to catch up to the tortoise, and for Homer to catch the bus.
In the case of Achilles and the tortoise, suppose that the tortoise runs at a constant speed of v metres per second (m/s) and gets a head start of distance d metres (m), and that Achilles runs at constant speed xv m/s with x > 1. It takes Achilles time d/xv seconds (s) to travel distance d and reach the point where the tortoise started, at which time the tortoise has travelled d/x m. It then takes further time d/x2v sec for Achilles to travel this new distance d/x m, at which time the tortoise has travelled another d/x2, and so on.
Thus, the time taken for Achilles to catch up is
-
seconds.
Since this is a finite quantity, Achilles will eventually catch the tortoise.
Similarly, for the Dichotomy assume that each of Homer's steps takes a time proportional to the distance covered by that step. Suppose that it takes time h seconds for Homer to complete the last half of the distance to the bus; then it will have taken h/2 sec for him to complete the second-last step, traversing the distance between one quarter and half of the way. The third-last step, covering the distance between one eighth and one quarter of the way to the bus, will take h/4 sec, and so on. The total time taken by Homer is, summing from k = 0 for the last step,
-
seconds.
Once again, this is a convergent sum: although Homer must pass through an infinite number of distance segments, most of these are infinitesimally short and the total time required is finite. So (provided it doesn't leave for 2h seconds) Homer will catch his bus.
In both cases, by moving at constant speeds (and in particular not stopping after each segment) Achilles will eventually catch the moving tortoise, and Homer the stationary bus. However, the solutions that employ geometric series have the advantage that they attempt to solve the paradoxes in their own terms, by denying the apparently paradoxical conclusions.
[edit] Proposed solution using calculus notation
- d = distance between runners
- t = time
[edit] Issues with the proposed calculus-based solution
A suggested problem with using calculus to try to solve Zeno's paradoxes is that this only addresses the geometry of the situation, and not its dynamics. It has been argued that the core of Zeno's paradoxes is the idea that one cannot finish the act of sequentially going through an infinite sequence, and while calculus shows that the sum of an infinite number of terms can be finite, calculus does not explain how one is able to finish going through an infinite number of points, if one has to go through these points one by one. Zeno's paradox points out that in order for Achilles to catch up with the Tortoise, Achilles must first perform an infinite number of acts, which seems to be impossible in and of itself, independent of how much time such an act would require.
Another way of putting this is as follows: If Zeno's paradox would say that "adding an infinite number of time intervals together would amount to an infinite amount of time", then the calculus-solution is perfectly correct in pointing out that adding an infinite number of intervals can add up to a finite amount of time. However, any descriptions of Zeno's paradox that talk about time make the paradox into a straw man: a weak (and indeed invalid) caricature of the much stronger and much simpler inherent paradox that does not at all consider any quantifications of time. Rather, this much simpler paradox simply states that: "for Achilles to capture the tortoise will require him to go beyond, and hence to finish, going through a series that has no finish, which is logically impossible". The calculus-based solution offers no insight into this much simpler, much more stinging, paradox.
A thought experiment used against the calculus-based solution is as follows. Imagine that Achilles notes the position occupied by the tortoise, and calls it first; after reaching that position, he once again notes the position the turtle has moved to, calling it second, and so on. If he catches up with the turtle in finite time, the counting process will be complete, and we could ask Achilles what the greatest number he counted to was. Here we encounter another paradox: while there is no "largest" number in the sequence, as for every finite number the turtle is still ahead of Achilles, there must be such a number because Achilles did stop counting.
[edit] Are space and time infinitely divisible?
Another proposed solution to some of the paradoxes is to consider that space and time are not infinitely divisible. Just because our number system enables us to give a number between any two numbers, it does not necessarily follow that there is a point in space between any two different points in space, and the same goes for time.
If space-time is not infinitely divisible (and thus not perfectly continuous), it is "discrete" (composed of “lumps” and “jumps”, as is experimentally observed in the field of quantum physics e.g. electron orbitals jumping from one level to another). This means that motion is, at the smallest physical level, a series of jumps from one quantum space-time coordinate to the next, each occurring over distance and time intervals that are not divisible into smaller measures.
Thus the total number of quantum jumps made while traversing from point A to point B is finite, and therefore there is no paradox.
[edit] Does motion involve a sequence of points?
Augustine of Hippo was the first to posit that time has no precise "moments," in his 4th century C.E. masterpiece, Confessions. In Book XI, section XI, paragraph 13, Augustine says, "truly, no time is completely present," and in Book XI, section XV, paragraph 20, Augustine says "the present, however, takes up no space."
Some people, including Peter Lynds, have proposed a solution based on this ancient premise. Lynds posits that the paradoxes arise because people have wrongly assumed that an object in motion has a determined relative position at any instant in time, thus rendering the body's motion static at that instant and enabling the impossible situation of the paradoxes to be derived. Lynds asserts that the correct resolution of the paradox lies in the realisation of the absence of an instant in time underlying a body's motion, and that regardless of however small the time interval, it is still always moving and its position constantly changing, so can never be determined at a time. Consequently, a body cannot be thought of as having a determined position at a particular instant in time while in motion, nor be fractionally dissected as such, as is assumed in the paradoxes (and their historically accepted solutions).
[edit] Conceptual and semantical approaches
Another approach is to deny that our conceptual account of motion as point-by-point movement through continuous space-time needs to match exactly with anything in the real world altogether. Thus, one could deny that time and space are ontological entities. That is, maybe we should give up on our Platonic view of reality, and say that time and space are simply conceptual constructs humans use to measure change, that the terms (space and time), though nouns, do not refer to any entities nor containers for entities, and that no thing is being divided up when one talks about "segments" of space or "points" in time.
Similarly, one can say that the number of "acts" involved in anything is merely a matter of human convention and labeling. In the constant-pace scenario, one could consider the whole sequence to be one "act," ten "acts," or an infinite number of "acts." No matter how the events are labeled, the tortoise will follow the same trajectory over time, and all of the acts will be "finished" by the time the tortoise reaches the finish line. Thus, the labeling of acts is arbitrary and has nothing to do with the underlying physical process being described and that it is possible to "finish" an infinite sequence of acts.
[edit] The notion of different orders of infinity
Some people state that the dichotomy paradox merely makes the point that the points on a continuum cannot be counted — that from any point, there is no next point to proceed to. However, it is not clear how this comment resolves the paradox. Indeed, as one variant of Zeno's paradox would state: if there is no next point, how can one even move at all? Also, it is not clear what this comment has to do with different orders of infinity: the rational numbers are countable, i.e. of the same order of infinity as the natural numbers, but on the rational number line, there is for any rational number still no next rational number either.
[edit] Status of the paradoxes today
Mathematicians thought they had done away with Zeno's paradoxes with the invention of the calculus and methods of handling infinite sequences by Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz in the 17th century, and then again when certain problems with their methods were resolved by the reformulation of the calculus and infinite series methods in the 19th century. Many philosophers, and certainly engineers, generally agree with the mathematical results.
Zeno's paradoxes are still hotly debated by philosophers in academic circles. Infinite processes have remained theoretically troublesome. L. E. J. Brouwer, a Dutch mathematician of the 19th and 20th century, and founder of the Intuitionist school, was the most prominent of those who rejected arguments, including proofs, involving infinities. In this he followed Leopold Kronecker, an earlier 19th century mathematician. Some claim that a rigorous formulation of the calculus (as the epsilon-delta version of Weierstrass and Cauchy in the 19th century or the equivalent and equally rigorous differential/infinitesimal version by Abraham Robinson in the 20th) has not resolved all problems involving infinities, including Zeno's.
[edit] Two other paradoxes as given by Aristotle
Paradox of Place:
- "… if everything that exists has a place, place too will have a place, and so on ad infinitum". (Aristotle Physics IV:1, 209a25)
Paradox of the Grain of Millet:
- "… there is no part of the millet that does not make a sound: for there is no reason why any such part should not in any length of time fail to move the air that the whole bushel moves in falling. In fact it does not of itself move even such a quantity of the air as it would move if this part were by itself: for no part even exists otherwise than potentially." (Aristotle Physics VII:5, 250a20)
For an expanded account of Zeno's arguments as presented by Aristotle, see: Simplicius' commentary On Aristotle's Physics.
[edit] The quantum Zeno effect
In recent time, physicists studying quantum mechanics have noticed that the dynamical evolution (motion) of a quantum system can be hindered (or even inhibited) through observation of the system. This effect is usually called the quantum Zeno effect as it is strongly reminiscent of Zeno's arrow paradox.
[edit] See also
[edit] Zeno's paradox in fiction
- Terry Pratchett in Pyramids combines the "Achilles and the tortoise" paradox and the arrow paradox to create the paradox of the arrow chasing the tortoise. [1]
- Dilbert has claimed that "No one ever wants to take more than half of what's left of the last doughnut. That's why I call it Xeno's doughnut" (2005-08-13).
- Umberto Eco in his 2004 novel (English language version 2005), The Mysterious Flame of Queen Loana, has the narrator (trying to recover from amnesia by going through old books and possessions) look at a recursive image and remark: "... Chinese boxes or Matrioshka dolls. Infinity, as seen through the eyes of a boy who has yet to study Zeno's paradox. The race towards an unreachable goal; neither the tortoise nor Achilles would ever have reached the last..."
- In Beyond Zork, there is a bridge named "Zeno's Bridge". It is impossible to fully cross this bridge, as you can only go a fraction of the distance to the destination.
- Phillip K. Dick in his 1953 short story The Indefatigable Frog uses Zeno's paradoxes as a basis for an experiment that places a shrinking frog in a tunnel, thus always increasing the length of the tunnel relative to the frog.
- Jorge Luis Borges explores various implications of Zeno's paradoxes in several of his stories and essays. In Avatars of the Tortoise (1932) he discusses how the argument of "Achilles and the tortoise" has manifested itself in the writings of Plato, William James, Lewis Carroll and many others, and goes on to argue that the paradox demonstrates the unreality of the visible world.
- Tom Stoppard in his play Jumpers references Zeno's paradox via the philosopher George; George manages to kill his tortoise Thumper while attempting to disprove Zeno's paradox.
- In Knight Rider Season 1 - Episode 09 Trust Doesn't Rust - 0:24:00 until 0:24:38 - a reference was made by KITT to an upcoming duel between him (KITT) and KARR (his earlier prototype). Kitt says: "...however since KARR is as powerful and as nearly indestructible as myself, Zeno's paradoxes should be affected." Devon Miles then explains who Zeno is. Kitt continues: "Zeno first postulated a question which my twin would most certainly be aware of: To wit; what would happen if an irresistible force met an immovable object?" In a later head-on-collision scene with KITT vs. KARR, Michael says: "..remember Zeno and that immovable object thing? We are about to find out the answer." Scholars do not attribute the irresistible force paradox to Zeno, and its origin is uncertain.
- In Harry Turtledove's novel Wisdom of the Fox, the character Rihwin employs the dichotomy paradox to trick a demon into carelessly halving its distance to him and thus leaving itself vulnerable.
[edit] Zeno's paradox in art
- Artist Mark Tansey created a painting titled Achilles and the Tortoise which shows the plume from a rising rocket, around which there are observers, which mimics the appearance of a nearby evergreen tree, with the rocket just short of passing the height of the tree. In the foreground are a group of people finishing the activity of planting a new tree. The image, suggesting the rocket as shown will not ever pass the height of the tree, and tantalizing the viewer with the idea that this has something to do with the processes being shown and that the new tree may or may not pass the rocket first--raises questions about how much static representations can have you understand what's being represented. Tansey is alluding to Zeno's own logic as a representation of what he's describing.
- The UK synthpop band Spray's first album contained a track titled "So Close," applies the fletcher's paradox to romance, including the telling line, "How close can I get when Cupid's arrow is always doomed to stall halfway to your heart?"
[edit] Notes and References
- R.M. Sainsbury, Paradoxes, Second Ed (Cambridge UP, 2003)
[edit] External links
- Advaita Vedanta
- http://www.mathacademy.com/pr/prime/articles/zeno_tort/index.asp
- Zeno's Paradoxes: A Timely Solution by Peter Lynds
- Zeno's Paradoxes of Motion: a section from Kevin Brown's book Reflections on Relativity
- BBC article on shortest time measured as of 2004: 10−16 seconds.
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry
- Zeno meets modern science
- Sankhya Philosophy
- Zeno's Paradoxes The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- The all or nothing dichotomy
- A layman's description & solution to Zeno's First Paradox
This article incorporates material from Zeno's paradox on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the GFDL.